Thomas Harriot: A Life in Science by Robyn Arianrhod

Thomas Harriot: A Life in Science by Robyn Arianrhod

Author:Robyn Arianrhod [Arianrhod, Robyn]
Language: eng
Format: epub
Tags: Biography & Autobiography, Science & Technology, history, Europe, Great Britain, General, Mathematics, History & Philosophy, science
ISBN: 9780190271855
Google: kjXcuQEACAAJ
Publisher: Oxford University Press
Published: 2019-11-15T00:31:03.443551+00:00


chapter 18

Atomic Speculations

Harriot’s theory of refraction involved a theory about matter itself, which he had tried out in his letter to Kepler. He was doing the same with his friend Torporley: it was during this period that Torporley wrote his notes of their discussions on the controversial subject of atomism.1

Torporley had the highest respect for Harriot as a mathematician and an experimentalist. In his 1602 book Diclides coelometricae, published not long after Harriot had discovered the law of refraction and while he was working on the trigonometry of the spherical triangle, Torporley had publicly praised him for dissipating, “by the splendor of undoubted truth, the philosophical clouds in which the world had been enveloped for many centuries.”2 But Diclides coelometricae is a rather odd book. It is on the topic of spherical trigonometry and combines obscure rhetoric, original theorems, and bizarre mnemonics. Unlike Harriot, Torporley did not shrink from publishing his work, no matter how slight. He seemed to have in mind astrologers rather than mathematicians as his readers. Astrology requires calculating angles between planets on the celestial sphere, and Torporley used astrological and other metaphors as mnemonic verses for remembering the required relationships between angles and distances in a spherical triangle. In view of Harriot’s work for Ralegh, perhaps Torporley had sailors in mind, too. Spherical triangles are needed to work out distances traveled along great circles, as Nunes’s work had also shown.

Torporley’s admiration of Harriot dimmed somewhat over the years—not because of Harriot’s mathematics, which Toporley would continue to praise highly, but because of his freethinking. In particular, Harriot’s use of “atoms” to explain refraction was “anathema” to Torporley’s religious sensibility, and he was piqued that his friend was “reviving” such a “pseudo-philosophy,” as he put it.3 As we saw in connection with Harriot’s embroilment in the Cerne Abbas investigation back in 1594, the ancient idea that everything was created from pre-existing atoms suggested the heretical converse concept ex nihilo nihil fit: from nothing, nothing comes. For Torporley, such a concept was a denial of the biblical account in which God created the world from nothing—and he felt he needed to look no further than Aristotle for support. The ancient Greek philosopher might have believed in the eternity of the world, but he was acceptable to the Christian mainstream not only on account of his geocentric crystalline heavenly spheres but also because he had argued against the existence of discrete, indivisible atoms as proposed by Leucippus and his student Democritus in the fifth century bce. (The Greek atomos means “indivisible.”)4

Aristotle argued on such grounds as continuity. Time and space are surely decomposed into smaller and smaller parts, ad infinitum, he said; otherwise there would be gaps in space and time. These gaps would lead to paradoxes, such as Zeno’s “Arrow.” (Zeno’s famous paradoxes have survived largely through Aristotle’s discussion of them.) If space and time were made of tiny discrete units—atoms of space, moments of time, which cannot be further subdivided—then consider a moving arrow. If you take a snapshot at each separate moment, the arrow is at rest.



Download



Copyright Disclaimer:
This site does not store any files on its server. We only index and link to content provided by other sites. Please contact the content providers to delete copyright contents if any and email us, we'll remove relevant links or contents immediately.